Why the human zygote is an organism (and why it matters)
By Paul Stark
In the public debate over embryo-destructive biomedical research, many people dismiss the claim that the human zygote and blastocyst/young embryo (early stages of human prenatal development just following conception) are human beings on the grounds that other cells and tissues—such as a patch of skin cells, or the sperm and egg—are also living and human, yet no one supposes that they are themselves human beings. But these critics are not well-informed of the biological facts. The crucial difference is that zygotes and embryos are organisms, and skin cells, sperm and egg are not. The zygote/embryo is a whole distinct human organism—that is, a human being, a self-developing member of the species Homo sapiens—at a very early stage of life. Other cells are mere parts of larger wholes, not individual organisms themselves.
But the term “organism” requires explanation. Dr. Maureen L. Condic, a Berkeley-educated neurobiologist and professor at the University of Utah School of Medicine, where she teaches human embryology, explains:
An organism is defined as “(1) a
complex structure of interdependent and subordinate elements whose
relations and properties are largely determined by their function in the
whole and (2) an individual constituted to carry on the activities of
life by means of organs separate in function but mutually dependent: a
living being.” This definition stresses the interaction of parts in the
context of a coordinated whole as the distinguishing feature of an
organism.
Based on this definition, it has been
proposed that human beings (including embryonic human beings) can be
reliably distinguished from human cells using the same kinds of criteria
scientists employ to distinguish different cell types: by examining
their composition and their pattern of behavior. A human being (i.e., a
human organism) is composed of characteristic human parts (cells,
proteins, RNA, DNA), yet it is different from a mere collection of cells
because it has the characteristic behavior of an organism: it acts in
an interdependent and coordinated manner to “carry on the activities of
life.” In contrast, collections of human cells are alive and carry on
the activities of cellular life, yet fail to exhibit coordinated
interactions directed towards any higher level of organization.
Collections of cells do not establish the complex, interrelated cellular
structures (tissues, organs, and organ systems) that exist in a whole,
living human being. Similarly, a human corpse is not a living human
organism, despite the presence of living human cells within the corpse,
precisely because this collection of human cells no longer functions as
an integrated unit.
From the moment of sperm-egg fusion, a
human zygote acts as a complete whole, with all the parts of the zygote
interacting in an orchestrated fashion to generate the structures and
relationships required for the zygote to continue developing towards its
mature state. Everything the sperm and egg do prior to their fusion is
uniquely ordered towards promoting the binding of these two cells.
Everything the zygote does from the point of sperm-egg fusion onward is
uniquely ordered to prevent further binding of sperm and to promote the
preservation and development of the zygote itself. The zygote acts
immediately and decisively to initiate a program of development that
will, if uninterrupted by accident, disease, or external intervention,
proceed seamlessly through formation of the genitive body, birth,
childhood, adolescence, maturity, and aging, ending with death. This
coordinated behavior is the very hallmark of an organism.
Mere human cells, in contrast, are
composed of human DNA and other human molecules, but they show no global
organization beyond that intrinsic to cells in isolation. A human skin
cell removed from a mature body and maintained in the laboratory will
continue to live and will divide many times to produce a large mass of
cells, but it will not re-establish the whole organism from which it was
removed; it will not regenerate an entire human body in culture.
Although embryogenesis begins with a single-cell zygote, the complex,
integrated process of embryogenesis is the activity of an organism, not
the activity of a cell.
Based on a scientific description of
fertilization, fusion of sperm and egg in the “moment of conception”
generates a new human cell, the zygote, with composition and behavior
distinct from that of either gamete. Moreover, this cell is not merely a
unique human cell, but a cell with all the properties of a fully
complete (albeit immature) human organism; it is “an individual
constituted to carry on the activities of life by means of organs
separate in function but mutually dependent: a living being.”
[T]he embryo comes into existence at
sperm-egg fusion … a human organism is fully present from the beginning,
controlling and directing all of the developmental events that occur
throughout life. This view of the embryo is objective, based on the
universally accepted scientific method of distinguishing different cell
types from each other, and it is consistent with the factual evidence.
It is entirely independent of any specific ethical, moral, political, or
religious view of human life or of human embryos. Indeed, this definition
does not directly address the central ethical questions surrounding the
embryo: What value ought society to place on human life at the earliest
stages of development? Does the human embryo possess the same right to
life as do human beings at later developmental stages? A neutral
examination of the factual evidence merely establishes the onset of a
new human life at a scientifically well defined “moment of conception,” a
conclusion that unequivocally indicates that human embryos from the
zygote stage forward are indeed living individuals of the human
species—human beings.
Science, then, tells us what the embryo is: an individual human
organism, a human being, at the embryonic stage of life. It cannot tell
us how the embryo ought to be treated, which is a moral (rather than
scientific) question.But if it is true (as pro-life advocates argue) that human beings as such have intrinsic moral value—that there is a fundamental equality among all members of our species, irrespective of size, age, ability and condition of dependency—then we may not destroy embryonic human beings for their stem cells any more than we may kill and harvest the useful parts of a 10-year-old child for the benefit of others.
Editor’s note. Paul Stark is Communications Assistant for Minnesota Citizens Concerned for Life, NRLC’s state affiliate. This appears at prolifemn.blogspot.com
Source: NRLC News
No comments:
Post a Comment